Overview: Objects in Measure Theory – Serlo

In the following articles on measure theory, we will gradually introduce various mathematical objects. These articles tell a story in which we will follow possible considerations of a mathematician, so we introduce new objects only when we really need them.

This article summarizes the objects in a compact way, so you can easily compare them.

Set systems Bearbeiten

To-Do:

Link Vitali-set, update all links.

The basis of measure theory is always a large basic set  , for which we want to assign a measure to subsets   that is, a number   that indicates how large   is. In many cases, however, not every subset   is suitable for such an assignment. For instance the Banach-Tarski paradox or the Vitali sets show this.

Those sets to which, we can assign a suitable measure   will simply be called measurable. We put them into a set system  . So the   is a set containing sets itself (like a bag in which there are even more bags), e.g.   with  .

To do computations with measures (i.e., addition, subtraction), we would like to perform operations with the sets, like unions  , intersections   or taking complements  . And this without "getting kicked out of  ", if possible. In mathematics, one therefore classifies set systems   into different types, depending on how many operations we can perform without getting kickes out of   and on other nice properties which they may satisfy:

 
Types of set systems. An arrow meas "is a generalization of".
  • The  -algebra is the most special and most frequently encountered set system type. Here we can "afford relatively many operations" which avoids problems of the kind "  is not defined on this set".   is an -algebra if and only if
  1.  
  2.  
  3. If a sequence of sets   is in   , then also  
  • An algebra (of sets) also satisfies these 3 axioms, but the 3rd is only required to hold for finite sequences  . The " " here stands for a countably infinite union of sets. If one omits it, then "only" finite sequences are allowed and one gets a more general set system. That is, there are "more algebras than  -algebras". A set system   is an algebra if and only if
  1.  
  2.  
  3. If a sequence of sets   is in   , then also  
  • A  -ring (also denoted  ) satisfies all conditions of the  -algebra, except for 1. That is, we also allow set systems containing only smaller sets. E.g., there could be a maximal set   containing all  . A system   is a   ring if and only if
  1.  
  2. Immer wenn eine Folge aus Mengen   in   liegt, dann ist auch  

Sometimes it is required as an additional condition that   is not empty, i.e.  . As soon as a ring   contains any set  , it always contains also the empty set  .

  • A ring (of sets)   is obtained equivalently by taking away from the  -ring the  -property. That means, we allow only finite   in our condition. From the axioms of the  -algebra only the 2nd and the 3rd in "finite" form are valid:
  1.  
  2. If a sequence of sets   is in   , then also  
  • * The Dynkin-system   is a separate type of set system. We will need it later to describe when measures match. The 3 axioms are:
  1.  
  2. For every pair of sets   with   we have  
  3. For countably many, pairwise disjoint sets   we have  .

Further set systems, that do not appear in the articles, are:

  • The monotone class  : a type of set system containing all limits of monotonically increasing or decreasing set sequences  . That means,
  1. If   form a monotonically increasing sequence, i.e.,  , then we have  
  2. If   form a monotonically decreasing sequence, i.e.,  , then we have  
  • The semi-ring is a generalization of the ring. The essential point is that   no longer lies in  , but only needs to be represented by a disjoint union of sets from it. The condition   (which always holds on rings) must thus be required separately. Instead of union stability one also demands cut stability:
  1.  
  2.  
  3. For   there exist disjoint sets  , such that  

Functions on sets Bearbeiten

Additive functions on sets Bearbeiten

On the set systems defined above, we now try to define functions   (or  ) that intuitively measure the "size" of a set. The intuition "measure a size" can be translated into several desirable properties. For example, an empty set should have size 0, so  . The more of these properties hold, the more the function   matches our intuition to measure the size of sets.

Depending on how many and which of these desirable properties are satisfied by  , we divide these functions into different classes. The most specific class is the measure, which has relatively many good properties and is therefore often used in mathematics, e.g., with in probability theory and statistics.

 
Relationship between 4 set systems. An arrow means "is a generalization of".
  • A measure   is a function on a  -algebra   with the quite intuitive property that the empty set has measure 0 and when joining sets that do not overlap, their measures must also be added:
  1.  
  2.   is  -additive, i.e.,  
  • A pre-measure   is in principle the same as a measure, but needs to be defined only on a  -ring   . So the set   can be in  , but doesn't need to be. Thus it holds that
  1.  
  2.   is  -additive, i.e.,  
  • A volume   on a ring   is a kind of "measure without  -property for additivity". So we require the additivity only for finite unions:
  1.  
  2.   is additive, i.e.,  
  • A continuous volume   on a ring   needs - as the name suggests - to be continuous:
  1.  
  2.   is additive
  3.  , as soon as a sequence of sets   converges monotonically increasingly or decreasingly to   . For monotonically decreasing sequences, we further require   nötig.

In a sense a measure is a " -volume". However, since measures appear much more often in mathematics than volumes, they are given an own name.

Subadditive functions on sets Bearbeiten

The following two classes of functions are not additive, but only sub-additive and therefore get their own letter  . I.e., if one unites, for example, a set with   and one with   there could be   (or we could have any number  )! This contradicts our intuition of "measuring a size". Therefore we give the functions a separate symbol  .

 
Every outer measure is an outer volume
  • The outer volume on the power set   is defined in analogy to the volume above. But instead of additivity, one only requires sub-additivity:
  1.  
  2.   is sub-additive, so from   we get  
  • An outer measure on the power set   is the  -version of the outer volume. That is, subadditivity is required even for countably infinite unions instead of finite unions. Thus the sub-additivity becomes a  -sub-additivity, where the   stands for "countably infinitely many".
  1.  
  2.   is  -sub-additive, so from   we get  

Examples: separating set system definitions Bearbeiten

The definitions of the set systems above are quite abstract and it is not obvious why some of them might not be equivalent. In the following examples, we will see how to separate the set system types

 

That means, we find examples that are of one but not a second type, respectively. In addition, you may find some (out of many possible) visualizations for those abstract definitions.


Example (Rings vs.  -rings)

We construct a set system in which "limiting sets" are not contained: Let   be a sequence of real numbers. These are elements of the interval  . We choose the basic set   to be slightly larger (this is perfectly allowed) and define the set system

 

i.e., all half-open intervals with endpoints from the sequence. This is not yet a ring. But we can make it a ring:

Let   be the set system of all finite unions and intersections of intervals from   (which are again finite unions of half-open intervals with   as endpoints). The system   is a ring (the "ring generated by  "), but   is not a  -ring: the limiting sets

 

are not included. However, we can turn   into a  -ring by including the "limiting sets"   for all  . The set system

 

is again a  -ring (and thus also a ring).

Example ( -algebras vs.  -rings)

We copy the setting from the previous example: The set system   consists of all intervals   with endpoints in the sequence   . We choose the basis set to be   (see figure).

The set system   generates a ring   (by finite unions and intersections). Joining it with the limit sets   yields a  -ring

 

However, the set system   is not a  -algebra, since it does not contain the basic set   (likewise the empty set   is not contained). In a sense, the set system is "too small". We can make it a  -algebra: For this we add   and the empty set  , as well as the complement sets   for all  . From these sets we again form all arbitrary unions us intersections. and add them to the set system.

The result is a  -algebra   consisting of arbitrary unions of half-open intervals, with endpoints in  .

The only difference to   is that 2 is also allowed as endpoint and the empty set   is included.  -algebras can hence thought to be larger than mere  -rings.

We can make   even larger by adding a finite set of arbitrary points   to the set of allowed endpoints. From this we can construct a "larger   algebra"   by choosing   as a set system of arbitrary unions of half-open intervals between the endpoints   (which is shown in the figure above).


Example ( -Algebren vs. Algebren)

We use again the setting of the two examples above: On the interval   we define a sequence   of endpoints  .

The set system  , which consists of arbitrary finite unions of intervals of the form   is a ring of sets. However, it is not a   ring.

If we add 1 to the possible endpoints   (that is,   are allowed as endpoints of half-open intervals), and also allow countably infinite unions, we obtain a  -ring  . However, it is not a  -algebra, since it does not contain  .

If we add an additional 2 to the possible endpoints, we get a  -algebra  . Now, if we add finitely many more arbitrary endpoints, we still end up with  -algebras, which are, however, larger, and will be denoted by  .

The  -algebras   and   can be very easily transformed back into an algebra by taking out the endpoint 1.

We define the set system   to contain any countable unions of intervals with the same endpoints as those from  , except 1. Then   is an algebra, because   contains  . But taking it out destroys the  -property. That is, a countable union of sets (which contains, say, 1 as an endpoint) need no longer be in  .

Similarly, we can transform the  -algebra   into an algebra   by removing the endpoint 1. The  -property will then no longer hold.